Procedural abstraction
-
slide: The correctness calculus
In slide [10-correctness] correctness axioms have been given for
assignment, sequential composition, conditional statements
and iteration.
These axioms rely on the side-effect free nature
of expressions in the programming language.
Also, they assume convertibility between
programming language expressions and the expressions
used in the assertion language.
The assignment axiom states that for any post-condition Q we
can derive the (weakest) pre-condition by substituting the value e
assigned to the variable x for x in Q.
This axiom is related to the weakest pre-condition calculus
introduced by [Dijkstra76].
It is perhaps the most basic axiom in the correctness calculus
for imperative programs.
As an example, consider the assignment and
the requirement .
Applying the assignment axiom we have .
Consequently, when we are able to prove that P implies ,
we have, by virtue of the first consequence rule, proved that
.
The next rule, for sequential composition, allows
us to break a program (fragment) into parts.
For convenience, the correctness formulae for multiple
program fragments that are composed in sequential order are
often organized as a so-called proof outline of the form
.
When sufficiently detailed, proof outlines may be regarded
as a proof.
For example, the proof outline
constitutes a proof for the invariance property discussed earlier.
Clearly, the correctness formula for the two individual components
can be proved by applying the assignment axiom.
Using the sequential composition rule, these components
can now be easily glued together.
As a third rule, we have a rule for conditional statements of the form
.
As an example, consider the correctness formula
.
All we need to prove, by virtue of the inference rule
for conditional statements, is that
which (again) immediately follows from the assignment axiom.
As the last rule for proving correctness, we present here
the inference rule for iterative (while) statements.
The rule states that whenever we can prove that a certain
invariant I is maintained when executing the body of
the while statement (provided that the condition b is satisfied)
then, when terminating the loop,
we know that both I and hold.
As an example, the formula
while () i--;
trivially follows from the while rule by taking I to be true.
Actually, the while rule plays a crucial role in constructing
verifiable algorithms in a structured way.
The central idea, advocated among others by [Gries], is
to develop the algorithm around a well-chosen invariant.
Several heuristics may be applied to find the proper invariant
starting from the requirements expressed in the (output) predicate
stating the post-condition.
In addition to the assignment axiom and the basic inference rules
related to the major constructs of imperative programming languages,
we may use so-called structural rules to facilitate
the actual proof of a correctness formula.
The first structural (consequence) rule states that
we may replace a particular pre-condition for which we
can prove a correctness formula (pertaining to a program fragment S)
by any pre-condition of which the original pre-condition
is a consequence, in other words which is stronger than the original
pre-condition.
Similarly, we may replace a post-condition for which we
know a correctness formula to hold by any post-condition
that is weaker than the original post-condition.
As an example, suppose that we have proved the formula
then we may, by simultaneously applying the two consequence rules,
derive the formula
which amounts to strengthening the pre-condition
and weakening the post-condition.
The intuition justifying this derivation
is that we can safely promise less and require more,
as it were.
Finally, the rule most important to us in the present context
is the inference rule characterizing correctness
under procedural abstraction.
Assuming that we have a function m with formal parameter x
(for convenience we assume we have only one parameter, but this
can easily be generalized to multiple parameters), of which
the (function) body consists of .
Now, moreover, assume that we can prove for an arbitrary expression
e the correctness formula ,
with e substituted for the formal parameter x in both
the conditions and the function body, then we also have
that , provided
that P and Q do not contain references to local variables
of the function m.
In other words, we may abstract from a complex program fragment
by defining a function or procedure
and use the original (local) correctness proof
by properly substituting actual parameters for formal parameters.
The procedural abstraction rule, which allows us
to employ functions to perform correct operations,
may be regarded as the basic construct needed to verify
that an object embodies a (client/server) contract.
[]
readme
course
preface
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
appendix
lectures
resources
eliens@cs.vu.nl

draft version 0.1 (15/7/2001)